SIN
SUMMARY
The concepts of vice and virtue in the era of the Society are examined. The
distinction can be made and maintained but the Axioms pass full responsibility
for such moral judgements to individuals. The role of the Society is solely
to decide, in the light of its Aim, whether or not it should approve of, or
condemn, such personal decisions.
In the uncertain world of the Axioms it may seem that the age-old distinction
between vice and virtue cannot be maintained. The Principles 1.3 and 2.2
require
the Society of HumanKind to regard every aspect of the human character and all
its qualities as equally valuable. How then can it make any distinction
between those activities, pursuits or pleasures that are 'right' and those that
are 'wrong'?
Elsewhere in the founding books of the Society the achievement of its Aim is
used as a measure of human conduct. However, the Treatise on the Individual
concludes that, prior to our reunification following our escape from death, the
Society cannot definitely say which actions or attributes of humanity
contribute to the achievement of the Aim of the Society, and which detract from
it. Such judgements can only properly be made after, and not at any moment
before the apocalypse of our translation into immortals.
Which seems to leave the Society with no means or measure to pass judgement on
the actions or behaviour of any of its living adherents and followers.
Specifically, the problem facing the Society is that the Principle 2.2 appears
to preclude it, during its mortal era, from the condemnation or suppression of
any form of behaviour by any individual, either among its own adherents or
humanity in general.
Predecessors of the Society had the advantage of an external source of
authority in dealing with this problem, if only the laws of history or some
other form of predestination for humanity. They were able to draw upon that
authority to justify their categorisation of human behaviour into either vice
or virtue. No such unearthly measure is available to the Society.
The Society cannot avoid or ignore this difficulty. If it is to pursue its
Aim it must make day-to-day decisions about which aspects of human behaviour it
will encourage and which it will condemn. The preceding discussion has
established that it must do so without the hindsight that the achievement of
its Aim will provide. Such judgements will also be subject to the Axiomatic
uncertainty about the infinite consequences of any of our moral, or indeed
other, decisions set out in the Treatise on Knowledge. How is it possible
for the Society to maintain any distinction between virtue and vice?
Yet it is bound to find itself required to so. No-one can believe that vice
and virtue will vanish from the world merely on the appearance of the Society.
Nor will the need to make moral judgements disappear from the same cause.
So, despite the apparent impossibility of doing so, the Society must find some
way to make and apply such judgements both to its adherents and to others.
A search for a solution to this vexatious difficulty starts from a recognition
that the problems faced by the Society arise because the Axioms remove all
moral authority from the universe. They then prevent the Society from putting
itself in place of that lost authority, by removing all certainty from human
judgement. But those same Axioms also present the Society with an opportunity.
Because the Society can justly claim that the Axioms leave it free of any
obligation to fill the role of a moral authority, and prevent it from
pretending that it, or any other human institution, has the right or the power
to prescribe the moral conduct of individuals. Unlike its predecessors
therefore, the Society is left free by its founding ideas to reject any
suggestion that it should be the maker and enforcer of moral rules. With that
liberty it can then plunge headlong into the relativism so feared by moral
philosophers and others. With the freedom granted by the Axioms the Society
is able to choose not to follow the practice of its predecessors, and refuse to
put itself in the position of rule-maker or model in moral matters. Rather it
can be, and is, the judge or arbitrator of the moral decisions made by its
individual adherents and others.
In that new role the Society of HumanKind aims to avoid, wherever possible, any
general pronouncement on the proper moral conduct of individuals. Instead
it requires those who
advocate any particular action or pattern of behaviour to show that it
contributes to the achievement of the Objective of the Dogma and/or its Aim.
If no such prime facie defence can be established, then the Society begins with
the presumption that the behaviour should be condemned. Not because it has
reached any judgement on what damage might be caused to the achievement of its
Aim, since, as has already been concluded in this Essay and elsewhere, the
Axioms remove all means finally to assess that issue. But because from its
base in the Axioms it is able to say that a claim to a virtuous life can only
be made where an individual devotes the whole of his time, and all of his
skill and knowledge to a faithful attempt to pursue of the Objective of the
Dogma and the Aim of the Society.
In the era of the Society of HumanKind, virtue is therefore found in a sincere,
whole-hearted and full time devotion and commitment to the Objective of the
Dogma and its
Aim. To the extent that any conduct or pattern of life deviates or detracts
from that
total devotion to the welfare of the human species, the Society can properly
judge it to be vice, and treat it as such.
Clearly, in an imperfect and uncertain world such judgements should be tempered
with both caution and compassion. Debate and discussion on the propriety or
otherwise of any proposed or actual behaviour might lead to the conclusion that
any damage caused to the Conditions of the Dogma is likely to be marginal, and
is more than compensated by other beneficial effects; for example, in the
maintenance of our social order, in the growth of our skills and knowledge, or
elsewhere in our social or intellectual life. There is a great benefit in
allowing an element of fluidity on issues of vice and virtue in the era of the
Society. It opens up the possibility, to put it no higher, that indulgences
in some pleasures which fall short of its strict measure of virtue, may
nevertheless meet with the tacit approval of the Society.
However, any approval given to any of our pursuits or pleasures by the Society
must depend upon good evidence that, in sum, any harm they do is judged to be
more than compensated by the contribution they make. As a final note, it will
be rare that any such generally applicable judgements will be reached. If so,
they should be the subject of a Credenda issued by the World Council of Elders.
The strands of the somewhat complex discussion of this Essay can now be drawn
together into a general rule for the practice of the Society in these matters.
The Society will not seek to establish itself as an authority on questions of
vice and virtue. Nor will it impose a rigid conformity on its followers in
these matters. In the era of the Society individuals will take responsibility
for their own standards of conduct.
They will however, have to convince their neighbours, through open debate and
discussion within the normal framework of decision-making within the Society,
that their behaviour is compatible with the Aim, Duty and Responsibility of the
Society. If they fail to do so, they may properly be judged to be vicious.
That stance of the Society on these issues has a further benefit. Every
aspect of human behaviour, including those claiming to be the most obviously
virtuous, will be open to this process of continuous scrutiny and justification.
The Axioms and the Dogma transform questions of vice and virtue. In the era
of the Society each and every individual will assume personal responsibility
for their own moral actions and decisions. The Treatise on Morality makes
that inescapable burden clear. The role of the Society will not be to decide
questions of individual morality. Its task will be to consider whether or not
it should, as a body, accept or reject justifications of a particular moral
decision, or pattern of behaviour, put forward by its proponents. The result
may be a Credenda on the subject where the World Council of Elders judges, and
whole Society concurs, that that action is necessary for the better
preservation of the Conditions of the Dogma and the pursuit of its Aim.
Membership of the Society will impose a harsh and unrewarding self-discipline
in these matters. Even after the full establishment of the Society, and the
creation of formal structures to aid in these decisions, that burden will be
onerous. Every individual adherent of the Society in each generation will be
left with the task of choosing which standards of conduct they are to adopt,
and of justifying that choice. They will also be called upon to judge the
present conduct of their fellows against the criteria of the maintenance of the
Conditions of the Dogma and the achievement of the Aim of the Society in the
uncertain world of the Axioms. As is repeatedly said, here in these Essays
and elsewhere, the Axioms and Dogma are no panacea for the social and moral
problems of humanity. They only provide a base on which we can build a new
meaning and purpose for our existence.
Despite all the complexities and uncertainties set out this Essay, vice can be
distinguished from virtue by an application of the Axioms, Dogma and
Principles. The fundamental method used is one familiar in earlier
ideologies. It is to identify the purpose and motivation of any action or
decision, and then to judge what its effect is likely to be. Neither an
acceptance of the Axioms nor the choice of the Dogma, nor even the emergence of
the Society of HumanKind will remove good and evil from the world. The
meaning of those words will change, but humanity will still need to find ways
to make the distinction.
|