5
OF PEACE
SUMMARY
Acceptance of the Axioms of the Society leaves humankind alone in the universe.
The liberating consequence is that we are responsible our own fate. Human
existence is precarious and our own best interests are served by unity,
diversity and peace between us. The Treatise concludes by noting that that is
also what is needed to achieve the Aim of the Society of HumanKind.
The Axioms are summarised by the proposition that we are alone. That is not
to say that our species is the sole representative of humankind, nor that other
intelligent life-forms may not exist in the universe. In the uncertain era of
the Society of HumanKind such unequivocal statements cannot safely be made.
But what the Society does say, in the light of its Axioms and following from
its choice of the Dogma, is that the safety, survival and salvation of
humankind is entirely and solely in our own hands.
The Axioms tell us that there is no omnipotent power or being to guide and
protect our species, nor any inevitable progression in our history to give
predictability and safety to our existence. Indeed, by attributing our
origins and our development to chance the Axioms imply that human history is a
unique series of events, with no inherent meaning or purpose. The practical
effect of these implications of the Axioms is to expose humanity to the utter
uncertainty set out in the Treatise of Knowledge.
At first sight that may seem an entirely negative and destructive outcome of an
acceptance of the Axioms. Yet they also give rise to the emancipating
consequence that the future of our species is not preordained, and the
discovery that we are truly free to choose our own fate. By surrendering the
illusion of the possibility of certainty in human knowledge we gain the liberty
to choose our destiny for ourselves. But freedom on this scale, real freedom,
arouses in us the fears of childhood; of inadequacy and of the possibility of
catastrophic failure. That fear is justified, because our situation in the
universe is indeed precarious.
As far we are aware our entire species originates on, and is confined to, a
single planet on the remote edge of a galaxy that, to our present knowledge,
contains no other humanly habitable environment. On our home planet we are
totally dependent on the continued presence of a layer of gases clinging to its
surface. A brief removal or slight alteration in the composition of our
atmosphere could instantly destroy us all.
At the same time seas cover four fifths of the surface of our world, a habitat
hostile to humanity. Even on the habitable parts of the land surface of our
world we are obliged to struggle with the elements to feed, clothe and protect
ourselves. While we do so, we must breathe continuously, and feed, drink and
sleep at regular frequent intervals. To survive as a species we must
undertake complex social and physical behaviour in order to reproduce in a
manner that is temporarily disabling and fraught with injurious risk to one
half of our kind, and results in young who are totally dependent for many
years. In all and on any detached view, our emergence as a dominant life form
on our planet must be regarded as surprising. Our qualifications for
permanent occupation of that position, or even long term survival as a species,
can also only be assessed as poor.
Earlier ideas of the nature and purpose of human existence have, on occasion,
made much of the superficial observation that many of the features of our world
are supportive of human life. Those systems of ideas have even gone so far as
to say that those features are proof of the existence of their God, or whatever
they posit as the originator or creator of our species. But in doing so they
neglect the equally valid, but opposite, form of that argument; which is, that
we could not have emerged nor survived as a species in our present form had we
not been, or rapidly become, well adapted to our environment. Those, now
largely discredited, defences of God and his competitors also ignore
observations, such as those set out in this Treatise, which tend to show that
we are not, in fact, well equipped or adapted to exist in even our fragile
world. In sum and on any balanced view, the occurrence and continuing
precariousness of human existence are both indeed remarkable.
Yet our history is a constant repetition of themes of death and destruction
directed against each other for reasons which, given the perspective of a harsh
and uncaring universe, must raise doubts about our collective sanity. The
present generation has, for example, amassed an arsenal of weapons whose sole
use is the destruction of human beings and whose capacity is sufficient to
destroy our entire world and every member of our species many times over.
That capacity has, moreover, been acquired and developed with great difficulty,
by the application of some of our best skills and abilities, and at enormous
cost in terms of the alternative use to which that expenditure and effort could
have been put. And the only justification advanced for developing that
tremendous capacity to kill each other is that it is required to protect us
from each other. Therein lies the insanity. The era of the Society of
HumanKind will mark an end to such madness.
The means and methods by which the Society of HumanKind will finally bring a
permanent peace between the different varieties of humankind are both complex
and novel in human experience. An understanding of those means and methods is
gained from four major sources in these founding books of the Society.
It begins with a grasp of the consequences of the Society's double choice: first,
of the Objective of the Dogma as the purpose of our lives; that is, to save ourselves
by discovering a means to extend our lives beyond death, and second, of its adoption of
its Aim; which is, to use the opportunity so gained to reunite all past,
present and future generations of humankind in a new immortal existence. On
that base are constructed the Principle 2.1; which shows the impossibility of
making any reliable estimate of the relative value of any of the attributes of
any member of our species during our lives, and the Principle 3.1; which points
to co-operation with others of our kind as our only recourse when faced with
any real difficulty.
Taken together, those two Principles show that an achievement of the Objective
of the Dogma and Aim of the Society is best served by widening rather then
reducing the range of qualities, characteristics and capacities available
within the human species, and by then maintaining peaceful and cooperative social
conditions which will allow that greater human diversity to be combined and focussed
on our survival and development. The greater the variety existing in the total
human population and the more closely we are combined together, the better
equipped we will be as a species to face the unpredictable challenges and risks
of the future, including of course those arising from the pursuit of the Objective
of the Dogma and the Aim of the Society. In seeking to preserve and extend
human variety and difference within stable and peaceful communities the Society
is thus concerned not only to protect and preserve every living individual but
also to foster and encourage their unique individuality as the Treatise of
the Individual makes explicit.
The view of Society of HumanKind is therefore, that instead of being feared as
it has too often been in the past, variation and difference in all its forms
must be fostered and encouraged in the human species and its society. The
Society will argue that the vital interest of every member of humanity is best
pursued by encouraging and preserving the widest possible range of diversity
and difference in our species, rather than by its reduction, suppression or
elimination. The Society of Humanity will thereby bring humanity to understand
that, far from being a cause for conflict, the existence of difference within our
species, from whatever cause, should be regarded as a source of joy and hope.
Having set out the views of the Society on questions of variation and
difference within the human family it remains to translate those conclusions
into a practical programme of day-to-day activities. As the earlier discussion
shows, all forms of violence and aggressive conflict between individuals and
groups, not just those based on real or perceived individual, national, social,
political or racial difference, ought to become a rare aberration after the
establishment of the Society of HumanKind.
Regrettably however, our history provides a mass of lamentable evidence to
dampen that hope. It contains innumerable episodes where we have striven, or
have been driven, to kill one another on the least pretext, despite the
existence of generally accepted and well-founded moral codes that condemn such
behaviour. It is unsafe therefore, to rely on the establishment of the
Society of HumanKind to eliminate violent and self-destructive behaviour from
humankind, since its predecessors among our social institutions have failed to
do so in the past. If any inference can be drawn from our history on this
subject it must surely be that it would be wiser to assume that our species
has, or has developed, self-destructive qualities and characteristics that are
too deeply ingrained and too common ever to be wholly suppressed.
The Society of HumanKind must therefore take it to be vital to the discharge of
its Duty that, within the bounds of its own Principles, it should do all it can
to shape our social lives so that any violent or destructive capacity we may
have is not turned against the order of our communities, nor used in any other
way to bring about the risk of our extinction. To that end the Society can,
and should, advocate and foster its own definition of the desired state of
human society. Its stated aim should be the creation of a world-wide, but
locally based, community of all humanity that displays sufficient peace,
stability and continuity to enable the qualities of every individual, including
those which have the potential to be turned to violence or destruction, to be
employed to further our survival and the progress of our knowledge.
In that effort the Society will have to overcome deep-seated difficulties.
Among the patterns of behaviour that have, in the past, most commonly
threatened the peace of human society, are the powerful impulses of
territoriality, personal and familial aggrandisement, competition for
dominance, and the urge to gain power over others. These seem to be
especially common in the male part of our species. The Society recognises on
other grounds that these characteristics are not necessarily harmful in
themselves. In our primeval period there were, no doubt, good and beneficial
reasons for our possession of them, and for toleration of their expression.
And it would be wrong to presume those violent and aggressive qualities will
never again be needed to counter some presently unforeseeable threat of
destruction to our species. But in the search for peace in human society they
represent the gravest risk to our social order, and hence our survival, that
the Society can identify with any confidence and yet also hope to control.
It cannot be denied that it is possible to develop human social structures that
will deal with this problem. Our history also provides many examples of
communities that exhibit both stability and peace, at least in their internal
relationships. That not infrequent record of success in maintaining peaceful
communities despite the apparent universality of a potential for conflict and
self-destruction in the human species, must give hope to the Society in its
search for a social order that will support the pursuit of its Aim.
Aggression, competition and similar potentially violent behaviour may be common
characteristics of humanity, but they are not the only, nor even the most
important. Our common experience of social life may show a pattern of mutual
conflict, but it is at the same time a chronicle of the invariable communal
nature of our species, and of our unavoidable interdependence.
There has never been a period in our history when humanity has not sought to
live in groups and communities, and struggled to maintain peaceful co-operative
relationships within them. Our past contains more than sufficient evidence to
show that our species has a strong desire and hope for safety and security by
and through the establishment of settled and stable communities, and a longing
to live at peace with those we recognise as our own kind, which has been and
remains an almost universal human aspiration. It is on that equally powerful
quality of humanity, on its communal nature and on our need for mutually
supportive relationships with others of our kind, that the Society must seek to
build a social order which will contain, and try to turn to advantage, the
destructive tendencies of our species.
That set of observations provides the key to the creation and maintenance of
peace by the Society of HumanKind. Every member of our species shares a hope
for peace through a co-operative communal life. Through the Society of
HumanKind and by its Principle of Unity they can be drawn to recognise and
accept their fundamental dependence on, and their commonalty with, not just
their neighbours, compatriots and those they may regard as their like kind, but
the whole of humanity. On those foundations the Society can build a form of
social order that will successfully contain and safely redirect our self
destructive proclivities.
And the simple fact is that that basis for peace is laid as soon as the Axioms
are accepted. As is concluded in the Principle 3.1, acceptance of the Axioms
requires us to abandon our childish delusions of omnipotence, reject the
possibility that there is some power or purpose that will save us from
ourselves, and come at last to accept and understand that we have no hope or
resource beyond each other if we are to undertake any task beyond the capacity
of any single individual.
Such tasks include not only our individual survival and our battle both with
our hostile environment and to preserve its limited resources, but also the
Objective of the Dogma if we make that the purpose of our lives. The lesson
of the Axioms is therefore, that co-operation and mutual support is the only
path by which humanity may hope, first to anticipate, and then to avoid, the
dangers, both within and between our communities, that constantly threaten to
annihilate us both individually and as a species. Any detached assessment of
our own individual best interests both in the present and for the future must
lead us to ridicule any suggestion that we should spend any more effort than is
absolutely necessary on conflict between ourselves, or on developing or
refining means to kill each other.
These arguments and conclusions are at their most powerful when applied to the
conduct of adherents of the Society of HumanKind. The force of their desire
for peace is immeasurably increased by their affirmation of the Aim, Duty and
Responsibility of the Society of HumanKind. By that decision they reinforce
their natural desire for peace with recognition of new and powerful duties and
obligations. They thereby come to understand that the living generation is
the embodiment and repository of the contribution of every member of every
earlier generation to the survival and progress of our species. It is, at the
same time, the sole custodian of the hopes of the whole of humanity past,
present and future, for salvation and an afterlife beyond the finality of death.
The passion for peace of adherents of the Society will not only arise from the
common, simple, desire of humanity to live in a stable, protective social
order. Adherents will also know that any action, mistake, neglect or omission
that seriously undermines our peace threatens the destruction of the entire
living generation, and with it the extinction of our species. Any such error
will put at risk the aspirations of the deceased and of the yet to be born, to
share in the eternal life of the reunification of humanity which will follow
the realisation of the Aim of the Society. To the Society and its adherents
therefore, peace among humanity is indistinguishable from the pursuit of its
Aim. To them, the growth and progress of the Society and the spread of peace,
are one and the same thing.
So that, whatever its success in the pursuit of its Aim, and irrespective of
any progress toward the achievement of the Objective of the Dogma, the
establishment of the Society of HumanKind will at least have one beneficial
consequence. It will provide every member of our species with both a means
and a powerful reason to live at permanent peace in their environment, and with
all their neighbours.
|